W.D. (later Sir David) Ross
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Sir William David Ross (15 April 1877 – 5 May 1971), known as David Ross but usually cited as W. D. Ross, was a Scottish Aristotelian philosopher, translator, WWI veteran, civil servant, and university administrator. His best-known work is The Right and the Good (1930), in which he developed a pluralist, deontological form of intuitionist ethics in response to G. E. Moore's consequentialist form of intuitionism. Ross also critically edited and translated a number of Aristotle's works, such as his 12-volume translation of Aristotle together with
John Alexander Smith John Alexander Smith (21 April 1863 – 19 December 1939) was a British idealist philosopher, who was the Jowett Lecturer of philosophy at Balliol College, Oxford from 1896 to 1910, and Waynflete Professor of Moral and Metaphysical Philosoph ...
, and wrote on other Greek philosophy.


Life

William David Ross was born in Thurso, Caithness in the north of Scotland the son of John Ross (1835-1905). He spent most of his first six years as a child in southern India. He was educated at the Royal High School, Edinburgh, and the University of Edinburgh. In 1895, he gained a first class MA honours degree in
classics Classics or classical studies is the study of classical antiquity. In the Western world, classics traditionally refers to the study of Classical Greek and Roman literature and their related original languages, Ancient Greek and Latin. Classics ...
. He completed his studies at
Balliol College, Oxford Balliol College () is one of the constituent colleges of the University of Oxford in England. One of Oxford's oldest colleges, it was founded around 1263 by John I de Balliol, a landowner from Barnard Castle in County Durham, who provided the f ...
, with a First in
Classical Moderations Honour Moderations (or ''Mods'') are a set of examinations at the University of Oxford at the end of the first part of some degree courses (e.g., Greats or '' Literae Humaniores''). Honour Moderations candidates have a class awarded (hence the ' ...
in 1898 and a First in Literae Humaniores ('Greats', a combination of philosophy and ancient history) in 1900. He was made a Fellow of
Merton College Merton College (in full: The House or College of Scholars of Merton in the University of Oxford) is one of the constituent colleges of the University of Oxford in England. Its foundation can be traced back to the 1260s when Walter de Merton, ch ...
in 1900, a position he held until 1945; he was elected to a tutorial fellowship at Oriel College in October 1902. With the outbreak of World War I, Ross joined the army in 1915 with a commission on the special list. He held a series of positions involved with the supply of munitions. At the time of the armistice he held the rank of major and was Deputy Assistant Secretary in the Ministry of Munitions. He was made an
Officer of the Order of the British Empire The Most Excellent Order of the British Empire is a British order of chivalry, rewarding contributions to the arts and sciences, work with charitable and welfare organisations, and public service outside the civil service. It was established o ...
in 1918 in recognition of his wartime service. For his post-war services to various public bodies he was made a
Knight Commander of the Order of the British Empire The Most Excellent Order of the British Empire is a British order of chivalry, rewarding contributions to the arts and sciences, work with charitable and welfare organisations, and public service outside the civil service. It was established ...
in 1938. Ross was White's Professor of Moral Philosophy (1923–1928), Provost of
Oriel College, Oxford Oriel College () is a constituent college of the University of Oxford in Oxford, England. Located in Oriel Square, the college has the distinction of being the oldest royal foundation in Oxford (a title formerly claimed by University College, wh ...
(1929–1947), Vice-Chancellor of the University of Oxford from 1941 to 1944 and Pro-Vice-Chancellor (1944–1947). He was president of the
Aristotelian Society The Aristotelian Society for the Systematic Study of Philosophy, more generally known as the Aristotelian Society, is a philosophical society in London. History Aristotelian Society was founded at a meeting on 19 April 1880, at 17 Bloomsbury Squar ...
from 1939 to 1940. He was elected a Fellow of the British Academy and was its President from 1936–to 1940.
G. N. Clark Sir George Norman Clark, (27 February 1890 – 6 February 1979) was an English historian, academic and British Army officer. He was the Chichele Professor of Economic History at the University of Oxford from 1931 to 1943 and the Regius Profes ...

‘Sir David Ross’
'' Proceedings of the British Academy'', 57 (1971), 525–43
Of the many governmental committees on which he served one was the Civil Service Tribunal, of which he was chairman. One of his two colleagues was Leonard Woolf, who thought that the whole system of fixing governmental remuneration should be on the same basis as the US model, dividing the civil service into a relatively small number of pay grades. Ross did not agree with this radical proposal. In 1947 he was appointed chairman of the first
Royal Commission on the Press, United Kingdom Three Royal Commissions on the Press were held in the United Kingdom during the 20th century. The first (1947–49) proposed the creation of a General Council of the Press to govern behaviour, promote consumer interests and conduct research into t ...
. He was elected an honorary fellow of Trinity College Dublin in 1947. He died in Oxford on 5 May 1971. He is memorialised on his parents' grave in the Grange Cemetery in Edinburgh.


Family

His younger brother was Rev Donald George Ross (1879-1943). He married Edith Ogden in 1906 and they had four daughters, Margaret (who married
Robin Harrison Alick Robin Walsham Harrison CBE (15 November 1900 – 18 May 1969) was an English academic, Warden of Merton College, Oxford, from 1963 until his death in 1969. Life Robin Harrison was born on 15 November 1900 in Hambledon, Surrey and was ...
), Eleanor, Rosalind (who married John Miller Martin), and Katharine. Edith died in 1953. He was a cousin of Arthur Berriedale Keith, Berriedale Keith.


Ross's ethical theory

W. D. Ross was a Moral realism, moral realist, a non-naturalist, and an intuitionist. He argued that there are moral truths. He wrote:
The moral order...is just as much part of the fundamental nature of the universe (and...of any possible universe in which there are moral agents at all) as is the spatial or numerical structure expressed in the axioms of geometry or arithmetic.
Thus, according to Ross, the claim that something is good is true if that thing really is good. Ross also agreed with G.E. Moore, G.E. Moore's claim that any attempt to define ethical statements solely in terms of statements about the natural world commits the naturalistic fallacy. Furthermore, the terms "right" and "good" are ''indefinable''. This means not only that they cannot be defined in terms of natural properties but also that it is not possible to define one in terms of the other. Ross rejected Moore's consequentialism, consequentialist ethics. According to consequentialist theories, what people ought to do is determined only by whether their actions will bring about the best. By contrast, Ross argues that maximising the good is only one of several ''prima facie'' duties (prima facie obligations) which play a role in determining what a person ought to do in any given case.


Duties

In ''The Right and the Good,'' Ross lists seven ''prima facie'' duties, without claiming his list to be all-inclusive: fidelity; reparation; gratitude; justice; beneficence; non-maleficence; and self-improvement. In any given situation, any number of these prima facie duties may apply. In the case of ethical dilemmas, they may even contradict one another. Someone could have a prima facie duty of reparation, say, a duty to help people who helped you move house, move house themselves, and a prima facie duty of fidelity, such as taking your children on a promised trip to the park, and these could conflict. Nonetheless, there can never be a true ethical dilemma, Ross would argue, because one of the prima facie duties in a given situation is always the weightiest, and over-rules all the others. This is thus the ''absolute obligation'' or ''absolute duty'', the action that the person ought to perform. It is frequently argued, however, that Ross should have used the term "pro tanto" rather than "prima facie". Shelly Kagan, for example, wrote: Explaining the difference between pro tanto and prima facie, Kagan wrote: "A ''pro tanto'' reason has genuine weight, but nonetheless may be outweighed by other considerations. Thus, calling a reason a pro tanto reason is to be distinguished from calling it a ''prima facie'' reason, which I take to involve an epistemological qualification: a prima facie reason ''appears'' to be a reason, but may actually not be a reason at all."


Values and intuition

According to Ross, self-evident intuition shows that there are four kinds of things that are intrinsically good: pleasure, knowledge, virtue and justice. "Virtue" refers to actions or dispositions to act from the appropriate motives, for example, from the desire to do one's duty. "Justice", on the other hand, is about happiness in proportion to merit. As such, pleasure, knowledge and virtue all concern states of mind, in contrast to justice, which concerns a relation between two states of mind. These values come in degrees and are comparable with each other. Ross holds that virtue has the highest value while pleasure has the lowest value. He goes so far as to suggest that "''no'' amount of pleasure is equal to any amount of virtue, that in fact virtue belongs to a higher order of value". Values can also be compared within each category, for example, well-grounded knowledge of general principle is more valuable than weakly grounded knowledge of isolated matters of fact. According to Ross's ''intuitionism'', we can know moral truths through intuition, for example, that it is wrong to lie or that knowledge is intrinsically good. Intuitions involve a direct apprehension that is not mediated by inferences or deductions: they are self-evident and therefore not in need of any additional proof. This ability is not inborn but has to be developed on the way to reaching mental maturity. But in its fully developed form, we can know moral truths just as well as we can know mathematical truths like the axioms of geometry or arithmetic. This self-evident knowledge is limited to general principles: we can come to know the ''prima facie'' duties this way but not our ''absolute'' duty in a particular situation: what we should do all things considered. All we can do is consult perception to determine which prima facie duty has the highest normative weight in this particular case, even though this usually does not amount to knowledge proper due to the complexity involved in most specific cases.


Criticism and influence

A frequent criticism of Ross's ethics is that it is unsystematic and often fails to provide clear-cut ethical answers. Another is that "moral intuitions" are not a reliable basis for ethics, because they are fallible, can vary widely from individual to individual, and are often rooted in our evolutionary past in ways that should make us suspicious of their capacity to track moral truth. Additionally there is no consideration of the consequence of the action undertaken, as with all deontological approaches. Ross's deontological pluralism was a true innovation and provided a plausible alternative to Kantian deontology. His ethical intuitionism found few followers among his contemporaries but has seen a revival by the end of the 20th and the beginning of the 21st century. Among the philosophers influenced by ''The Right and the Good'' are Philip Stratton-Lake, Robert Audi, Michael Huemer, and C.D. Broad.


Selected works

* 1908
''Nicomachean Ethics''
Translated by W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press. * 1923: ''iarchive:in.ernet.dli.2015.536932, Aristotle'' * 1924
''Aristotle's Metaphysics''
* 1927: 'The Basis of Objective Judgments in Ethics'. ''International Journal of Ethics'', 37:113–127. * 1930: ''iarchive:rightgood0000ross, The Right and the Good'' * 1936: ''Aristotle's Physics'' * 1939
''Foundations of Ethics''
* 1949: ''Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics'' * 1951: ''iarchive:platostheoryofid0000ross, Plato's Theory of Ideas'' * 1954: ''iarchive:kantsethicaltheo0000ross, Kant’s Ethical Theory: A Commentary on the Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten,'' Oxford: Oxford University Press.


References


Further reading

* G. N. Clark
‘Sir David Ross’
'' Proceedings of the British Academy'', 57 (1971), 525–43 * Phillips, David. Rossian Ethics: W.D. Ross and Contemporary Moral Theory. New York: Oxford University Press, 2019. * Stout, A. K. 1967
'Ross, William David'
In P. Edwards (ed.), ''The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy''. New York: Macmillan: 216–217. * Stratton-Lake, Philip. 2002. 'Introduction'. In Ross, W. D. 1930. ''The Right and the Good''. Oxford: Oxford University Press. * Timmons, Mark. 2003
'Moral Writings and The Right and the Good'.
[Book Review] ''Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews''


External links

*
"William David Ross"
by David L. Simpson in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2012
''William David Ross''
a biography and online lectures at the Gifford Lectures website *Cooley, Ken.
Sir David Ross's Pluralistic Theory of Duty (The Beginnings)
' {{DEFAULTSORT:Ross, W. D. 1877 births 1971 deaths People from Thurso People educated at the Royal High School, Edinburgh Alumni of Balliol College, Oxford Alumni of the University of Edinburgh British Army personnel of World War I Fellows of Oriel College, Oxford Honorary Fellows of Trinity College Dublin Knights Commander of the Order of the British Empire Scottish philosophers Moral realists Moral philosophers Philosophers of ethics and morality 20th-century British philosophers British scholars of ancient Greek philosophy Vice-Chancellors of the University of Oxford Pro-Vice-Chancellors of the University of Oxford Provosts of Oriel College, Oxford White's Professors of Moral Philosophy Presidents of the British Academy Presidents of the Aristotelian Society Greek–English translators 20th-century translators Fellows of the British Academy Fellows of Merton College, Oxford Presidents of the Classical Association